Blog | Subscribe | Free Trial | Contact Us | Cart | Donate | Planned Giving
Log In | Search
facebook
rss
twitter
  • CURRENT
    • Winter 2023 pdf
    • NEWSworthy: What’s Happening and What It Means to You
    • Blog
    • INSISTING ON LIFE
    • Pastoral Reflections
    • About Us
    • HLF In The News
    • LIBERTY TO DO WHAT? Hadley Arkes and Rusty Reno join George McKenna June 1, 2022 in New York
  • DINNER
    • GREAT DEFENDER OF LIFE DINNER 2022
    • HOST COMMITTEE Great Defender of Life Dinner 2022
    • Great Defender of Life 2022 Dinner Ticket
    • Great Defender of Life 2022 STUDENT or PREGNANCY CENTER STAFF Ticket
    • DINNER JOURNAL ADVERTISING 2022
  • ARCHIVE
    • Archive Spotlight
    • ISSUES IN HTML FORMAT
  • LEGACY
    • Planned Giving: Wills, Trusts, and Gifts of Stock
  • SHOP
    • Cart

Articles

Over 45 years of Life-Defending Articles At Your Fingertips
0 Comment

DEFINING DEATH, NOT DEFINING LIFE

26 Feb 2014
John Grondelski
Print Friendly, PDF & Email

 

The February 5, 2014 issue of the New England Journal of Medicine (NEJM) features an opinion piece by two bioethicists and a medical doctor vigorously defending a “brain death” definition of death against individual dissenters—such as the McMath family in California—in the name of ensuring “bright lines” on how society determines when someone is no longer part of society (http://www.nejm.org/doi/full/10.1056/NEJMp1400930.) What is less bright about this editorial are the philosophical axes being ground in the background.

         The authors—David C. Magnus, PhD, Benjamin S. Wilfond, MD., and Arthur L. Caplan, PhD—profess concern about the cases of two women: Marliese Muñoz in Texas, whose family wanted her taken off life support when the hospital (at first) wanted to keep her on it, and Jahi McMath in California, whose family insisted she be kept on life support when the hospital wanted to remove it (a court has since ruled that her family could transfer young Jahi to another facility, one willing to maintain her body on a ventilator, which they have done). 

          Without getting into the ethics of the McMath case, I want to focus on the NEJM article’s highly selective presentation of the Muñoz case. 

          Magnus, Wilfond, and Caplan admit that Muñoz was pregnant. They note she was “14 weeks pregnant when she died from pulmonary embolism” and that the Texas hospital initially refused to disconnect her from the respirator because of a “state law requiring that support not be terminated if a patient is pregnant.” They also acknowledge that “a pregnancy can be maintained even after the pregnant woman has met the neurologic criteria for death.”

          Unfortunately, the authors end their discussion without addressing a most relevant question: In the Muñoz case, were there one patient, or two? It is relevant because when there are two patients, basic medical ethics requires taking cognizance of the interests of both, starting with the elementary axiom, primum non nocere (first, do no harm). An honest ethical discussion must address that question; it must at least acknowledge that there is an argument to be made that life begins at conception, in which case the fate of her child would be a separate question from that of Marlise Muñoz herself. The authors cannot pretend that the question does not exist simply because they do not want to speak to it. 

         If human life begins at conception, then it is at least theoretically possible that the unborn child—as a patient—can have real medical interests independent of her mother. That contrast becomes even sharper if the child’s mother is declared to be dead. As modern bioethicists do not fail to remind us, it is possible to maintain the appearance of life even in a dead body, even though that appearance is of no practical benefit to the deceased. But if the body is a corpse receiving no benefit, neither is it being injured. On the other hand, the lack of benefit to the dead mother does not address the question of whether the medical procedure is of benefit to the unborn child.

          Professors Caplan and Magnus are honorable men, noted in the bioethics field. But honorable men ought not to get away with evading the question by claiming that “[w]hen a person is dead, life support has to end regardless of what parents, judges or legislators might want to believe . . . .” Such sophistry tries to decide questions of life and death by ignoring them, with the real-life consequences affecting other’s lives.

Without coming out and saying it in so many words, the NEJM article leaves the impression that, once Marlise Muñoz was declared dead, there was nothing else to be said. Not only does it ignore the fact that turning off the ventilator killed her unborn child, it maintains an insidious front of silence that refuses even to consider the possibility that another patient’s interests could have been at stake. 

          What is true of the end of life ought to be true of its beginning. Indeed, it should be more true of its beginnings, because a humane society is not one eager to usher members out, one foot on the edge of the grave and another on a banana peel.  For all the pooh-poohing about slippery-slope arguments, there is something fundamentally awry with a society that demands clarity as to when one ceases to be its member, but is willing to fudge all manner of ambiguity about when one joins. Such a society has embraced what Bl. John Paul properly called “a culture of death.”

The determination of life is, as the authors say, a “highly significant social boundary.” Yet, for more than four decades, the United States has feigned agnosticism about being able accurately (and officially) to demarcate its beginning.  A “wink, wink, nudge, nudge” approach to unspoken assumptions about where that boundary lies has made it possible for butchers like Kermit Gosnell to kill while the law looks the other way. (Gosnell was finally brought to justice only because a police investigation into his illegal drug business revealed the horrors taking place at his abortion clinic.) But I hold no illusion that the team of Magnus, Wilfond, and Caplan is going to call for “bright lines” at the beginning of life which might actually correspond with the biological “facts of life.”

*     *     *     *     *

—John M. Grondelski (Ph.D., Fordham) was associate dean of the School of Theology, Seton Hall University, South Orange, NJ (USA).

For more about Jahi McMath, see this piece by Wesley J. Smith:

 

           

454 people have visited this page. 1 have visited this page today.

Social Share

  • google-share

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Comments will not be posted until approved by a moderator in an effort to prevent spam and off-topic responses.

*
*

captcha *

Get the Human Life Review

subscribe to HLR

Recent Posts

Wyoming Bans Abortion Pills

22 Mar 2023

Legal Issues on Chemical Abortions

13 Mar 2023

HHS weighs declaring access to abortion a "public health emergency’

08 Mar 2023

CURRENT ISSUE

Anne Conlon Anne Hendershott B G Carter Brian Caulfield Christopher White Clarke Forsythe Colleen O’Hara Connie Marshner David Mills David Poecking David Quinn Diane Moriarty Dr. Donald DeMarco Edward Mechmann Edward Short Ellen Wilson Fielding Fr. Gerald E. Murray George McKenna Helen Alvaré Jane Sarah Jason Morgan Joe Bissonnette John Grondelski Kathryn Jean Lopez Kristan Hawkins Laura Echevarria Madeline Fry Schultz Maria McFadden Maffucci Mary Meehan Mary Rose Somarriba Meaghan Bond Nat Hentoff Nicholas Frankovich Patrick J. Flood Peter Pavia Rev. George G. Brooks Rev. Paul T. Stallsworth Stephen Vincent Tara Jernigan Ursula Hennessey Victor Lee Austin Vincenzina Santoro W. Ross Blackburn Wesley J. Smith William Murchison

Pages

  • Issues
  • Human Life Foundation Blog
  • About Us
  • Free Trial Issue
  • Contact Us
  • Shop
  • Planned Giving
  • TOPICS
  • GREAT DEFENDER OF LIFE DINNER

Follow Us On Twitter

Tweets by @HumanLifeReview

Find Us On Facebook

Human Life Review/Foundation

Search our Website

Contact Information

The Human Life Foundation, Inc.
The Human Life Review
271 Madison Avenue, Room 1005
New York, New York 10016
(212) 685-5210

Copyright (c) The Human Life Foundation.